The Lure of Philosophy in Sydney

James Franklin

Oct 01 2009

14 mins

Philosophy is a uniquely important subject, dealing as it does with the most important questions there are. Sydney has a unique way of doing it.

Does life have a meaning, and if so what is it? What can I be certain of, and how should I act when I am not certain? Why are the established truths of my tribe better than the primitive superstitions of your tribe? Why should I do as I’m told? Those are questions it is easy to avoid, in the rush to acquire goods and prestige. Even for many of a more serious outlook, they are questions easy to dismiss with excuses like “it’s all a matter of opinion” or “let’s get on with practical matters” or “they’re too hard”. They are questions that may be ignored, but they do not go away.

They are philosophical questions. There is a right way to approach them—you read the writings of the classical and recent philosophers and consider carefully their arguments back and forth. There are many wrong ways to approach them, such as choosing at random among the ideas your parents or friends or gurus have, or ideas that feel good. Or you can just not bother.

Sydney has a certain reputation for superficiality in this regard. A character in David Williamson’s Emerald City says, “No one in Sydney ever wastes time debating the meaning of life—it’s getting yourself a water frontage.” If you have a writers’ festival or a Conference on Happiness in Sydney, you do not normally expect philosophers to be invited. Caroline Jones’s radio series The Search for Meaning elicited the opinions of environmentalists, artists’ models, former prime ministers and herbalists, but not of any philosophers.

My book, Corrupting the Youth: A History of Philosophy in Australia, which is focused on Sydney, was reviewed in the Age and the Australian, but not in the Sydney Morning Herald, where the literary editor thought readers would not be interested.

Still, even Sydneysiders show an interest in philosophy from time to time. A lot of people turned up to see Alain de Botton at the Opera House, and last year there were an amazing number of people reading Richard Dawkins’s The God Delusion on the bus. Dawkins may be bad at philosophy—well, he is bad at philosophy—but he was certainly arguing directly about one of the classic philosophical issues, “Does God exist?”

And Sydney was, in a certain sense, started as a philosophical experiment. Dumping convicts was its purpose, certainly, but there was also a high-minded vision about what should happen to them when they got here, based on Enlightenment concepts of the reformability of humanity.

The vision is imaginatively realised in the first seal of New South Wales. On September 21, 1791, the colony was delighted by the arrival of His Majesty’s Ship Gorgon, bearing a quantity of food, fruit trees and cows, and a public seal, extremely well executed in silver. It bore a representation of convicts landing in Botany Bay, received by Industry (that is, an allegorical figure in a toga), who, surrounded by her attributes, a bale of merchandise, a beehive, a pickaxe, and a shovel, is releasing them from their fetters, and pointing to oxen ploughing, and a town rising on the summit of a hill … and for a motto, “Sic fortis Etruria crevit” (Thus Etruria grew strong) a quotation from the description of the Golden Age in the second book of Virgil’s Georgics.

The plan had some success, too, with a surprising number of petty thieves turning into respectable citizens. That is very unlike the religious formations from which the United States grew. Australia has continued to have a more secular approach to its institutions, that is, philosophical as opposed to religious. There was no established church, Sydney Grammar School and the universities were secular foundations, the state education systems were non-religious.

Whatever may be true of the philosophical shortcomings of the average Sydneysider, Sydney philosophers themselves have made a substantial contribution, and a distinctive one, well recognised in the wider philosophical world. We need to start with John Anderson, Professor of Philosophy at the University of Sydney for thirty years from 1927. He was Sydney’s best-known academic. He dominated the higher reaches of Sydney intellectual life for those thirty years. His students played a leading role for another thirty, not only in academia, but in politics, law, journalism and teaching.

Anderson’s arrival marked a sharp break which set Australian philosophy on its characteristic course. His philosophy was realist (in the sense of being concerned with the ways of working of real things in the world, rather than having our ideas as the central focus of philosophy). It was also materialist, atheist and more interested in criticism than in synthesis or moral uplift. Sydney philosophy, especially but not uniquely, has maintained those biases.

To be realist about something, such as ethics, as opposed to idealist or constructivist, is to believe it really exists, as opposed to being “in the eye of the beholder”. So what about, say, forces? Among the items in the world, such as physical objects, are there also forces—or are they just a way of talking about something else, such as accelerations? Here is an argument for realism about forces: put your two index fingers together lightly. Now press twice as hard. It feels different. There is no movement in either case. So you have felt a force. Therefore forces really exist. (Or … do they? Did you really feel just a difference in shape of the fingers? …) That is the kind of debate they have in philosophy—in the part of philosophy that looks at the foundations of science.

Anderson was also a materialist (meaning he thought there were only material things, not such items as immaterial minds or souls, angels, or disembodied numbers) and atheist (meaning he did not believe in any sort of god). That created trouble in the atmosphere of the 1930s and 1940s. His statements on why education should be free of religion were condemned by the New South Wales parliament in 1943 as “calculated to undermine the principles which constitute a Christian State”. His ideas were “calculated to undermine” Christian principles in both senses of “calculated”: Anderson calculated they would, and they were in the absolute calculated, as in likely, to undermine them. It is encouraging to see a parliament troubled by philosophy —and rightly: they were well aware that the state’s future schoolteachers had access to philosophical ideas almost entirely through him.

And Anderson had a view of philosophy itself as primarily critical. He wrote:

The work of the academic, qua academic, is criticism; and whatever his special field may be, his development of independent views will bring him into conflict with prevailing opinions and customary attitudes in the public arena and not merely among his fellow-professionals

It was said, “John Anderson had an answer to every conceivable question. It was ‘No’.” One follower wrote:

As regards students, Anderson contended that the morality of criticism would reject the current talk of their “corruption”. If this “corruption” means a departure from established views on the part of students, then the job of the university is to corrupt the youth.

He addressed that task directly, initiating an affair with a second-year undergraduate whom he eventually appointed a lecturer in his department.

This is a quote from David Stove, a Sydney philosopher who was a student of Anderson and admired his work, while believing his influence was morally bad. It gets to the point of what philosophy is for:

The influence Anderson exercised was purely, or as purely as a human influence can be, purely intellectual. I never felt anything like the force of his intellect. Disagreeing with Anderson was (to compare it with something most people have experienced), like playing chess against someone altogether above your own class. Your strongest pieces are, you cannot tell how, drained of all their powers, while on his side even pawns can do unheard-of things; and as though by invisible giant fingers, you are quickly crushed … He was in love with philosophy himself, and he communicated the love of it to others so effectively that many will have it while they live. This is the greatest service he did.

Yet for every person whom he made a philosopher he left ten people, I should say, with a respect for philosophy, and a recollection of what it is like to wrestle in earnest with desperately difficult intellectual questions. This may not sound much, but I think it is much. Whoever can remember what serious thinking is like, is to some extent armed against all the enemies of education. He is armed against the acknowledged leaders of the war against education, the educationists. He is armed against educational levellers of every kind. And he is armed against systems, such as Marxism, which pretend to answer every question out of a little holy catechism, and which just for that reason often act like a revelation on unfurnished minds.

One independent thinker who studied with Anderson and wrote of his influence was Sir John Kerr.

Then there was the Sydney Push, a group of intellectuals who hung around several Sydney pubs in the late 1950s and early 1960s, drinking and debating the evils of what they called “moralism”. They were, in Barry Humphries’s words, “a fraternity of middle-class desperates, journalists, drop-out academics, gamblers and poets manqués, and their doxies”. And according to feminists, a lot of sexist bastards. True, all true. But they had a number of Anderson’s students among them and they went in for some serious criticism. They had an influence they did not expect in creating “The Sixties”. One of their core members, Germaine Greer, produced one of the most influential of sixties books, The Female Eunuch. It is unusual among the feminist books of the time in not being about reform. “Privileged women will pluck at your sleeve and seek to enlist you in the ‘fight’ for reforms, but reforms are retrogressive.” As with all true Andersonians, it is all criticism.

Let us go back to something more abstract and less personal and deal with less emotionally charged questions such as whether forces exist. Two of Anderson’s main students to become philosophers were David Armstrong and David Stove.

Armstrong, who like Anderson was Challis Professor of Philosophy at the University of Sydney for thirty years, is known for his realist theory of universals. What are universals? The world consists of things and stuff: people, horses, water, atoms or whatever observation and science advise. Does it also consist of the properties of things, such as their colours and shapes? Those properties, called universals or repeatables because they can occur in many things—are they real? Or put in a more linguistic way, do adjectives, like blue, name something real? A confusing question. Armstrong says yes, universals are real—science depends on them. When Newton’s law of gravity describes how bodies attract, it says they attract in proportion to their masses, and mass is a universal. Laws of nature, Armstrong argues, are connections between universals. And you only perceive an apple in virtue of its shape and colour, so the shape and colour must be real, as they are what is affecting your senses.

That is an example of Sydney-style realist argument.

Next let us consider some logic, looking at the work of David Stove, who also became a philosopher at Sydney University. Since the ancient Greeks there has been discussion of the syllogism, an argument such as the following. Suppose you have premises 

            All men are mortal

            Socrates is a man

Then you can conclude with certainty that Socrates is mortal. It is impossible that the premises, “All men are mortal” and “Socrates is a man” should be true and the conclusion, “Socrates is mortal” should be false. That sort of deductive logic is well understood. It is essential in mathematics, for example.

Now suppose instead that you have the premises:

             99 per cent of men are mortal

            Socrates is a man

What should you conclude about whether Socrates is mortal? Well, you cannot be certain, since (according to the premises) some men are mortal and some not. Still, surely it’s likely, given that the vast majority of men are mortal, that Socrates is mortal. That is the sort of reasoning we use all the time when we say: nearly all plane flights land safely, so I’m relaxed on takeoff, or, most sufferers of disease X who take drug Y are cured, so it’s worth taking it in my case. So what is that “likely”? Stove said it was a matter of strict logic, just like the syllogism. He was one of the rather few people to explore the field of non-deductive logic, or logical probability. He argued that with those concepts, you could solve the “problem of induction”, which is the question why, having observed that all swans so far have been white, that gives you reason to believe that the next swan will be white.

Now let us move to a topic where everyone considers himself an expert, ethics. There, the debates are particularly intense between realists (who think there is an objective right and wrong) and constructivists or relativists (who think ethics is a matter of tribal custom or evolved behaviour that could easily have been different). Obviously that has major consequences for how you go about solving ethical conflicts. Anderson had a realist view of ethics, but a very peculiar one. He thought that some things were objectively good, such as—you guessed it—criticism, but he did not think it followed that anyone ought to do those things: he believed there were no “oughts”.

The more usual form of ethical realism has been mostly pursued by Catholic philosophers. Their view is that ethics is based on what they call “natural law”. That does not mean, “If God had meant us to fly he would have given us wings.” It means more like: persons have an inherent worth, and therefore, for example, destroying one is an evil. The former governor-general Sir William Deane explains it like this:

The basis of natural law is the belief that some things are innately right and some innately wrong, flowing from the nature of things, including our nature as human beings. That approach provides a philosophical basis for seeing such things as human rights as going deeper than any particular act of Parliament or what have you. That is not exclusively Catholic. It runs through Christian belief.

Deane’s approach has had consequences for Australia. He and another Catholic judge steeped in natural law theory, Sir Gerard Brennan, were the leaders of the High Court in the Mabo decision, which overthrew precedent over Aboriginal land rights in favour of a deeper moral value in the law, the equality of persons.

Only last year, the University of Notre Dame, Sydney, held an excellent conference with all the world’s leading thinkers on natural law ethics. The issues are still live.

Most of the above is about times long past. It is hard not to see a decline since the old days when giants walked the earth, but perhaps someone younger than me will be better able to discern great minds in the current generation. Professional philosophy in the last forty years has certainly expanded, and it has made a lot of money by venturing into fields like business ethics and bioethics. But it has been subject also to many stresses. There was a wave of post-sixties Marxism that created trouble in the 1970s, leading to the celebrated split of the Sydney University Philosophy Department. Then there was the juggernaut of French-inspired postmodernism from the 1980s, a form of resentment-fuelled constructivism that questions all attempts to reach the truth. Its end has been often predicted but is not yet in sight.

Still, virtue is not wholly extinct. At all Sydney’s universities and beyond, there are serious philosophers who get on with the job—for example, those in Sydney University’s Centre for the Foundations of Science.

You might like to join them.

This is an edited version of an address James Franklin recently gave at the Sydney Writers’ Festival. His book Corrupting the Youth: A History of Philosophy in Australia was published by Macleay Press in 2003.

Comments

Join the Conversation

Already a member?

What to read next

  • Letters: Authentic Art and the Disgrace of Wilgie Mia

    Madam: Archbishop Fisher (July-August 2024) does not resist the attacks on his church by the political, social or scientific atheists and those who insist on not being told what to do.

    Aug 29 2024

    6 mins

  • Aboriginal Culture is Young, Not Ancient

    To claim Aborigines have the world's oldest continuous culture is to misunderstand the meaning of culture, which continuously changes over time and location. For a culture not to change over time would be a reproach and certainly not a cause for celebration, for it would indicate that there had been no capacity to adapt. Clearly this has not been the case

    Aug 20 2024

    23 mins

  • Pennies for the Shark

    A friend and longtime supporter of Quadrant, Clive James sent us a poem in 2010, which we published in our December issue. Like the Taronga Park Aquarium he recalls in its 'mocked-up sandstone cave' it's not to be forgotten

    Aug 16 2024

    2 mins